Portfolio Choice with CRRA Utility (Merton-Samuelson)

Merton (1969) and Samuelson (1969) study the optimal portfolio choice of a consumer with constant relative risk aversion ρ  .1 At the end of period t  this consumer has assets at  , and is deciding how much to invest in a risky asset2 with a lognormally distributed return factor Rt+1   (its log return rt+1 = log Rt+1   is distributed normally), rt+1 = r + 𝜀t+1 ∼ 𝒩 (r,σ2)
                        𝜀  for 𝜀t+1 ∼  𝒩 (0,σ2)
             𝜀  . [ELogNorm  ]   reviews the well-known fact that in such a case the expectation of the return in levels (the ‘arithmetic’ mean; see [ArithmeticVSGeometric    ]  ) is             r+ (1∕2)σ2
𝔼t [Rt+1 ] = e      𝜀   so that for small r  and σ2𝜀  we will have an excellent approximation: defining r = r + (1∕2)σ2𝜀  , it will be true that 𝔼t[Rt+1 ] ≈ 1 + r (again see [ArithmeticVSGeometric    ]  ). For the rest of this handout, we will usually treat this approximation as an exact relationship.3

                 ≡r
              ◜---◞◟--◝
log 𝔼t[Rt+1] = r + 0.5σ2r
                      2
            = r◟-−-0◝.◜5σr◞
                  =r
(1)

Any at  NOT invested in the risky asset is assumed to be invested in a riskfree asset that earns return factor R =  er   . Importantly, the consumer is assumed to have no labor income and to face no risk aside from that caused by their investment in the risky asset.4 ,  5

Both papers consider a multiperiod optimization problem, but here we examine a consumer for whom period t  is the second-to-last period of life (the insights, and even the formulas, carry over to the multiperiod case).6

If the period-t  consumer invests proportion ς  in the risky asset, spending all available resources in the last period of life t + 1  will yield:

ct+1 =  (R(1 − ς) + Rt+1 ς)at
    =  (R + (R    − R )ς) a
       ◟------◝t+◜1------◞  t
             ≡ℜt+1

where ℜ
  t+1   is the realized arithmetic return factor for the portfolio.

The optimal portfolio share will be the one that maximizes expected utility:

ς = arg max  𝔼 [u(c   )]
        ς     t    t+1
(2)

and can be calculated numerically for any arbitrary distribution of rates of return.

Campbell and Viceira (2002) show that if we define the ‘equity premium’ as

                        2
φt+1 = rt+1 − r + (1 ∕2)σr
(3)

then for many distributions a good approximation to the portfolio rate of return (the log of the portfolio return factor) is obtained by7

                    2      2  2
𝔯t+1 =  r + ςφt+1 + ςσr∕2 − ς σr∕2.
(4)

Using this approximation, the expectation as of date t  of utility at date t + 1  is:8

                    − 1     1− ρ (1− ρ)ς(1− ς)σ2∕2   [ ςφ   (1−ρ)]
𝔼t [u(ct+1)] ≈ (1◟-−-ρ-)◝◜(atR-)--◞e----------r- 𝔼t-e--t+1----
                  constant < 0   ◟   excess retur◝n◜ utility factor ◞
(5)

where the first term is a negative constant under the usual assumption that relative risk aversion ρ > 1.

For the special (but reasonable) case of a lognormally distributed return, we can make substantial further progress, by obtaining an analytical approximation to the numerical optimum. In this case ς(1 − ρ)φt+1 ∼ 𝒩 (ς(1 − ρ)(φ − σ2 ∕2),(ς(1 − ρ))2σ2)
                                 r               r  (again using [LogELogNormTimes  ]  ). With a few extra lines of derivation we can show that the log of the expectation in (5) is9

      [         ]
log𝔼t  eςφt+1(1−ρ) = (1 − ρ)ςφ − (1 − ρ)ς(1 − ς)σ2r∕2 − ρ(1 − ρ)ς2σ2r∕2.
(6)

Substitute from (6) for the log of the expectation in (5) and note that the resulting expression simplifies because it contains (1 − ρ)ςσ2r∕2 − (1 − ρ)ςσ2r∕2 = 0  ; thus the log of the ‘excess return utility factor’ in (5) is

                         2 2
− (ρ − 1)ςφ − (ρ − 1)(− ρς σr∕2 )
(7)

and the ς  that minimizes the log will also minimize the level; minimizing this when ρ >  1  is equivalent to maximizing the terms multiplied by − (ρ − 1)  , so our problem reduces to

              2 2
maxς   ςφ − ρ ςσ r∕2

with FOC

φ − ςρσ2r = 0
           (  φ  )
       ς =   ----  .
             ρσ2r
(8)

Equation (8)10 says that the consumer allocates a higher proportion of net worth to the high-risk, high-return asset when

  1. the equity premium φ  is greater
  2. the consumer is less risk averse (ρ  is lower)
  3. riskiness σ2r  is less

If there is no excess return (φ = 0  ), nothing will be put in the risky asset. Similarly, if risk aversion or the variance of the risk is infinity, again nothing will be put in the risky asset.11

This formula hints at the existence of an ‘equity premium puzzle’ (Mehra and Prescott (1985)). Interpreting the risky asset as the aggregate stock market, the annual standard deviation of the log of U.S. stock returns has historically been about σr = 0.2  yielding σ2 = 0.04
 r  . Mehra and Prescott claim that the equity premium has been something like φ =  0.08  (eight percent). With risk aversion of ρ = 2  this formula implies that the share of risky assets in your portfolio should be 0.08∕0.08  or 100 percent! The fact that most people have less than 100 percent of their wealth invested in stocks is the ‘stockholding puzzle,’ the microeconomic manifestation of the equity premium puzzle (Haliassos and Bertaut (1995)).

To avoid the problems caused by a prediction of a risky portfolio share greater than one, we can calibrate the model with more modest expectations for the equity premium. Some researchers have argued that when evidence for other countries and longer time periods is taken into account, a plausible average value of the premium might be as low as three percent. The figures show the relationship between the portfolio share and relative risk aversion for a calibration that assumes a modest premium of 3 percent and a large standard deviation of σ = 0.2  . Even when risks are this high and the premium is this low, if relative risk aversion is close to logarithmic (ρ = 1  ) the investor wants to put well over half of the portfolio in the risky asset. Only for values of risk aversion greater than 2 does the predicted portfolio share reach plausible small values.

But remember that these calculations are all assuming that the consumer’s entire consumption spending is financed by asset income. If the consumer has other income (for example, labor or pension income) which is not perfectly correlated with returns on the risky asset, they should be willing to take more risk. Since, for most consumers, most of their future consumption will be financed from labor or transfer income, it is not surprising to learn that models calibrated to actual data on capital and noncapital income dynamics imply that people should be investing most of their non-human wealth in the risky asset (with reasonable values of ρ  ).

A final interesting question is what the expected rate of return on the consumer’s portfolio will be once the portfolio share in risky assets has been chosen optimally. Note first that (14) implies that

       𝔯t+1−r
log 𝔼t[e     ] = ςφ
(9)

while the variance of the log of the excess return factor for the portfolio is  2    2 2
σ𝔯 = ς σr.  Substituting the solution (8) for ς  into (9), we have

     (     )
        φ2
ςφ =   ---2
       ρ σr
   = (φ ∕σr)2∕ρ
(10)

which is an interesting formula for the excess return of the optimally chosen portfolio because the object φ∕σ
    r  (the excess return divided by the standard deviation) is a well-known tool in finance for evaluating the tradeoff between risk and return (the ‘Sharpe ratio’). Equation (10) says that the consumer will choose a portfolio that earns an excess return that is directly related to the (square of the) Sharpe ratio and inversely related to the risk aversion coefficient. Higher reward (per unit of risk) convinces the consumer to take the risk necessary to earn higher returns; but higher risk aversion convinces them to sacrifice (risky) return for safety.

Finally, we can ask what effect an exogenous increase in the risk of the risky asset has on the endogenous riskiness of the portfolio once the consumer has chosen optimally. The answer is surprising: The variance of the optimally-chosen portfolio is

       (  φ )2
ς2σ2r =   --2-  σ2r
       ( ρσr   )
         (φ∕ρ)2-
    =      σ2
            r
(11)

which is actually smaller when σ2
 r  is larger. Upon reflection, maybe this makes sense. Imagine that the consumer had adjusted his portfolio share in the risky asset downward just enough to restore the portfolio’s riskiness to its original level before the increase in risk. The consumer would now be bearing the same degree of risk but for a lower (mean) rate of return (because of his reduction in exposure to the risky asset). It makes intuitive sense that the consumer will not be satisfied with this “same riskiness, lower return” outcome and therefore that the undesirableness of the risky asset must have increased enough to make him want to hold even less than the amount that would return his portfolio’s riskiness to its original value.

Figure 1  Approximate Risky Share ς  Declines as Relative Risk Aversion ρ  Increases

PIC

Figure 2  The Approximation Error for the Portfolio Share in Risky Assets ς  Is Small

PIC

Note: The approximation error is computed by solving for the exactly optimal portfolio share numerically. See the Portfolio-CRRA-Derivations.nb Mathematica notebook for details.

A The Campbell and Viceira (2002) Approximation

For mathematical analysis (especially under the assumption of CRRA utility) it would be convenient if we could approximate the realized arithmetic portfolio return factor by the log of the realized geometric return factor          1−ς  ς
ℜt+1 = R    R t+1   , because then the logarithm of the return factor would be 𝔯t+1 =  r(1 − ς) + rt+1 ς = r + (rt+1 − r)ς = r + φt+1ς  and the realized ‘portfolio excess return’ would be simply 𝔯t+1 − r = ςφt+1   . Unfortunately, for ς  values well away from 0 and 1 (that is, for any interesting values of portfolio shares), the log of the geometric mean is a badly biased approximation to the log of the arithmetic mean when the variance of the risky asset is substantial.

Campbell and Viceira (2002)’s propose instead

                    2      2  2
𝔯t+1 ≈  r + ςφt+1 + ςσr∕2 − ς σ r∕2.
(12)

To see one virtue of this approximation,12 note (using [NormTimes ]   and [SumNormsIsNorm   ]  ) that since the mean and variance of φt+1ς  are respectively ς(r − σ2r∕2 − r)  and ς2σ2r  , [LogELogNormTimes   ]   implies that

log𝔼t [eφt+1ς] = ς(r − r − σ2r∕2) + ς2σ2r∕2
(13)

which means that exponentiating then taking the expectation then taking the logarithm of (4) gives

    log𝔼t[e𝔯t+1] = log er + log 𝔼t[eςφt+1] + log eςσ2r∕2−ς2σr2∕2
                                2       2 2       2      2  2
                = r + ς(r − r − σr∕2) + ς σr∕2 + ςσr∕2 − ς σr∕2
log 𝔼t[e𝔯t+1] − r = ς(r − r)
(14)

or, in words: The expected excess portfolio return is equal to the proportion invested in the risky asset times the expected return of the risky asset.13

References

   Ameriks, John, Andrew Caplin, Steven Laufer, and Stijn Van Nieuwerburgh (2011): “The Joy Of Giving Or Assisted Living? Using Strategic Surveys To Separate Public Care Aversion From Bequest Motives,” The Journal of Finance, 66(2), 519–561.

   Campbell, John Y., and Luis M. Viceira (2002): Appendix to ‘Strategic Asset Allocation: Portfolio Choice for Long-Term Investors’. Oxford University Press, USA, https://scholar.harvard.edu/files/campbell/files/bookapp.pdf.

   Carroll, Christopher D. (2023): “Solving Microeconomic Dynamic Stochastic Optimization Problems,” Econ-ARK REMARK.

   Haliassos, Michael, and Carol Bertaut (1995): “Why Do So Few Hold Stocks?,” The Economic Journal, 105, 1110–1129.

   Mehra, Rajnish, and Edward C. Prescott (1985): “The Equity Premium: A Puzzle,” Journal of Monetary Economics, 15, 145–61.

   Merton, Robert C. (1969): “Lifetime Portfolio Selection under Uncertainty: The Continuous Time Case,” Review of Economics and Statistics, 51, 247–257.

   Samuelson, Paul A. (1969): “Lifetime Portfolio Selection by Dynamic Stochastic Programming,” Review of Economics and Statistics, 51, 239–46.

   Samuelson, Paul A (1979): “Why we should not make mean log of wealth big though years to act are long,” Journal of Banking and Finance, 3(4), 305–307.