March 14, 2023, Christopher D. Carroll LucasAssetPrice
Lucas [1978] considers an economy populated by infinitely
many1
identical individual consumers. The only assets are a set of identical
infinitely-lived trees. Aggregate output is the fruit that falls from the trees, and
cannot be stored (it would rot!); because , the fruit is all
eaten:
| (1) |
where is consumption of fruit per person,
is the population,
measures the stock of trees, and
is the exogenous output of fruit that drops
from each tree. In a given year, each tree produces exactly the same amount of
fruit as every other tree, but
varies from year to year depending on the
weather.2
An economy like this, in which output arrives without any deliberate actions on the part of residents, is called an ‘endowment’ economy (or, sometimes, an ‘exchange’ economy).3
If there is a perfect capital market for trees, the price of trees
must be such that, each period, each (identical) consumer
does not want either to increase or to decrease their holding of
trees.4
If a tree is sold, the sale is assumed to occur after the existing owner receives
that period’s fruit ( is the ‘ex-dividend’ price). Total resources available to
consumer
in period
are the sum of the fruit received from the trees owned,
, plus the potential proceeds if the consumer were to sell all his
stock of trees,
. Total resources are divided into two uses: Current
consumption
and the purchase of trees for next period
at price
,
| (2) |
Consumer maximizes
Rewriting in the form of Bellman’s equation,
|
the first order condition tells us that
| (3) |
| (4) |
where is the return factor that measures the resources in period
that are the reward for owning a unit of trees at the end of
.
The Envelope theorem tells us that , so (4) becomes
| (5) |
Since all consumers are identical, , so henceforth we just call
consumption per capita
. Since aggregate consumption must equal
aggregate production because fruit cannot be stored, normalizing the
population to
and the stock of trees to
, equation (1)
becomes:
| (6) |
Substituting and
for
and
in (5) and then substituting
for
we get
| (7) |
We can rewrite this more simply if we define
| (8) |
is called the ‘stochastic discount factor’ because (a) it is stochastic
(thanks to the shocks between
and
that determine the value of
); and (b) it measures the rate at which all agents in this economy in
period
will discount a dividend received in a future period, e.g.
:
| (9) |
A corresponding equation will hold in period (and in period
and
beyond):
| (10) |
so we can use repeated substitution, e.g. of (10) into (9), to get
| (11) |
The ‘law of iterated expectations’ says that ;
given this, and noting that
, (11) becomes:
| (12) |
So, the price of the asset is the present discounted value of the stream of future
‘dividends,’ where the (potentially stochastic) factor by which (potentially
stochastic) dividends received in are discounted back to
is
.5
This is as far as we can go without making explicit assumptions about the
structure of utility. If utility is CRRA, substituting
into (7) yields
| (13) |
The particularly special case of logarithmic utility (which Lucas emphasizes)
corresponds to , implying
which (again using the law of
iterated expectations) allows us to simplify the second version of (13) to
If the price is bounded (it cannot ever go, for example, to a value
such that it would cost more than the economy’s entire output to buy a
single tree), it is possible to show that the term in this equation
goes to zero. Using the usual definition of the time preference factor as
where
is the time preference rate, the equilibrium price is:
or, equivalently, the ‘dividend-price ratio’ is always .
It may surprise you that the equilibrium price of trees today does not depend on the expected level of fruit output in the future. If the weather was bad this year, but is expected to return to normal next year (and, by definition, is expected to be equal to normal in subsequent years), you might think that the price today would mostly reflect the ‘normal’ value of fruit prodution that the trees produce, not the (temporarily low) value that happens to obtain today.
The above derivation says that intuition is wrong: Today’s price depends only on today’s output.
Nevertheless, the logic (higher future output is a reason for higher current prices) is not wrong; but it is (exactly) counterbalanced by another, and subtler, fact: Since future consumption will equal future fruit output, higher expected fruit output means lower marginal utility of consumption in that future period of (more) abundant fruit (basically, people are starving today, which reduces the attractiveness of cutting their consumption to buy trees that will produce more in a period when they expect not to be starving). These two forces are the manifestation of the (pure) income effect and substitution effect in this model (there is no human wealth, and therefore no human wealth effect). In our assumed special case of logarithmic utility, income and substitution effects are of the same size and opposite sign so the two forces exactly offset.
We can decompose the return factor attributable to ownership of a share of
capital (cf. (4)) by adding and subtracting in the numerator:
so the ‘rate of return’ is
| (14) |
which is a useful decomposition because the two components have natural interpretations: The first is a ‘capital gain’ (or loss), and the second can plausibly identified as ‘the interest rate’ paid by the asset (because it corresponds to income received regardless of whether the asset is liquidated).
In models that do not explicitly discuss asset pricing, the implicit assumption is usually that the price of capital is constant (which might be plausible if capital consists mostly of reproducible items like machines,6 rather than Lucas trees). In this case
|
says that the only risk in the rate of return is attributable to unpredictable variation in the size of dividend/interest payments. Indeed, if additional assumptions are made (e.g., perfect capital markets) that yield the conclusion that the interest rate matches the marginal product of capital, then such models generally imply that variation in returns (at least at high frequencies) is very small, because aggregate capital typically is very stable from one period to the next; if the aggregate production function is stable, this implies great stability in the marginal product of capital.
One of the subtler entries in Aristotle [350 BC]’s catalog of common human reasoning errors was the ‘fallacy of composition,’ in which the reasoner supposes that if a proposition is true of each element of a whole, then it must be true of the whole.
The Lucas model provides a counterexample. From the standpoint
of any individual (atomistic) agent, it is quite true that a decision to
save one more unit will yield greater future resources, in the amount
. But from the standpoint of the society as a whole, if everyone
decided to do the same thing (save one more unit), there would be no
effect on aggregate resources in period
. Put another way, for any
individual agent, it appears that the ‘marginal product of capital’ is
, but for the society as a whole the marginal product of capital is
zero.
The proposition that the return for society as a whole must be the same as the
return that is available to individuals is an error because it implicitly assumes
that there are no general equilibrium effects of a generalized desire to save more
(or, more broadly, there is no interaction between the decisions one person
makes and the decisions of another person). The Lucas model provides a
counterexample in which, if everyone’s preferences change (e.g., goes
down for everyone), the price of the future asset is affected – indeed, it is
affected in a way that is sufficient to exactly counteract the increased
desire for ownership of future dividends (since there is a fixed supply of
assets to be owned, the demand must be reconciled with that preexisting
supply).
Aristotle was a smart guy!
In the case where dividends are identically individually lognormally distributed,
, the appendix shows that
| (15) |
and thus the variances obey
| (16) |
Given that , this derivation yields some interesting insights:
The second point is surprising; ChatGPT correctly summarizes the usual received wisdom about risk aversion by saying “In general, an increase in risk aversion can cause a decrease in the overall stock market ...”7 The reason for this prediction is intuitive: an increase in risk aversion makes people want the risky asset less, and if they want it less one would think that the price should be lower. But no: an increase in risk aversion increases the price of the risky asset. The resolution of this conflict between ChatGPT and Lucas comes from realizing that the usual model (ChatGPT will always summarize ‘the usual model’) is one in which investors have access to a safe asset as well as a risky one, while in the Lucas model presented here the only asset available is risky.
The appendices derive various results about the solution to the model under
different assumptions. But, unfortunately, the model has analytical solutions
(like, ) or approximate analytical solutions only in special
circumstances. The accompanying DemARK notebook shows how to solve the
model numerically for a simple case where there is no such analytical solution
(the case where dividends follow an AR(1) process), and also shows how the
numerical solution compares with the approximate analytical solution in the
CRRA utility case.
When , we can rewrite (13) by multiplying the second term on the right
by
, yielding
| (17) |
and we can hypothesize that there is a solution with a constant ratio .
In that case this equation simplifes to
| (18) |
Suppose is identically individually distributed in every future period, so
that its expectation as of
is the same for any date
:
| (19) |
Now note that (18) can be rewritten as
| (20) |
To make further progress, suppose that the iid process for
the stochastic component of dividends is a mean-one lognormal:
so that
(see
), in which case
can be used to show
that8
| (21) |
and if we define the discount factor as then
;
substituting into (20),
| (22) |
So the log is
| (23) |
as asserted in the main text.
The polar alternative to IID shocks would be for dividends to follow a
random walk: . (Recall that this assumption
implies that the expected arithmetic growth rate for dividends is zero:
; later we will consider the case in
which dividends have a positive trend growth rate).
Now divide both sides of (13) by , and rewrite the object inside the
expectations operator by multiplying the first term by
and dividing the
second term by
, yielding
| (24) |
Note that our assumption here about the distribution of is identical
to the assumption about
above, so the expectation will be the same
.
Now hypothesize that there will be a solution under which the price-dividend
ratio is a constant; call it
:
| (25) |
but , while OverPlus says that
and ExpEps
says
, so taking the log of both sides of this equation therefore
yields
| (26) |
In the case of logarithmic utility (), this equation confirms our
earlier conclusion in the main text that the arithmetic interest rate must
be equal to the time preference rate in order for the economy to be in
equilibrium.
But with , the expression subtracted from
must be positive.
That is simply saying that if consumers have risk aversion higher than
that of logarithmic utility, the equilibrium price-dividend ratio must
be such that consumers expect a higher
to make them willing to
hold the asset. For example, in the case where
, the expression
becomes
| (27) |
which indicates that the arithmetic rate of return must be lower than the time
preference rate by the amount in order to induce consumers to hold the
risky asset. Remembering that, for a given dividend payout, a lower
must
be accomplished by a higher price, this says that the price of the risky asset will
be higher in the economy with
.
This equation seems puzzing because with a low enough time preference rate,
and with and
, it could possibly imply that
. If
prices are positive, this must mean that dividends are negative - which was ruled
out by assumption in the statement of the model (because aggregate
consumption is equal to aggregate dividends, and negative
would yield
undefined utility).
What this reveals is that the model has no solution unless people are sufficiently impatient. (This is another impatience condition like those articulated in PerfForesightCRRA and TractableBufferStock – in this case, you must be impatient enough to want to hold the risky asset despite its riskiness).
Recall our earlier assumption that ; that is, the arithmetic growth rate
of dividends is zero. If, instead, dividends had a positive growth factor
, the consequence is that a further subtraction from
is
:
| (28) |
This makes the impatience condition
| (29) |
The effect of growth on the required rate of return therefore depends on the sign
of . If
, positive growth increases the required rate of return and
makes the impatience condition easier to satisfy. By increasing the required rate
of return, for any given level of dividends the price must be lower than in the
case where
. How can an asset with growing dividends be worth less
than one with dividends that do not grow? The answer is that—because
consumption must be equal to dividends—growing dividends also mean
growing consumption, and an agent who knows that he will have a higher
consumption in the future will be less willing to pay for further increases
in this future level of consumption. Therefore, there are two effects in
play:
How compares to
determines which of these two effects dominates.
All of this finally puts us in position to calculate the price from the dividend, which we can do using an updated version of (22) which incorporates growth:9
| (30) |
from which we can directly read off the following propositions:
For any given , if
and the impatience condition is satisfied, the price
is higher when:
Aristotle. On Sophistical Refutations. The Wikipedia Foundation, 350 BC. URL https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sophistical_Refutations.
Robert E. Lucas. Asset prices in an exchange economy. Econometrica, 46:1429–1445, December 1978. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/1913837. Available at http://www.jstor.org/stable/1913837.
Rajnish Mehra and Edward C. Prescott. The equity premium: A puzzle. Journal of Monetary Economics, 15:145–61, 1985. URL http://ideas.repec.org/a/eee/moneco/v15y1985i2p145-161.html.