LiqConstr October 16, 2020 at 11:18pm, prior-source-commit: efd1d52
_________________________________________________________________________
Abstract
We provide the analytical explanation of the interactions between precautionary
saving and liquidity constraints. The effects of liquidity constraints and risks
are similar because both stem from the same source: a concavification of the
consumption function. Since a more concave consumption function exhibits
heightened prudence, both constraints and risks strengthen the precautionary
saving motive. In addition, we explain the apparently contradictory results that
constraints and risks in some cases intensify, but in other cases weaken the
precautionary saving motive. The central insight is that the effect of introducing an
additional constraint or risk depends on whether it interacts with pre-existing
constraints or risks. If it does not interact with any pre-existing constraints
or risks, it intensifies the precautionary motive. If it does interact, it may
reduce the precautionary motive in earlier periods at some levels of wealth.
1Carroll: Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, email: ccarroll@jhu.edu 2Holm: Department of Economics, University of Oslo, email: martin.b.holm@outlook.com 3Kimball: Department of Economics, University of Colorado at Boulder, email: miles.kimball@colorado.edu
Dashboard: | https://econ-ark.org/materials/LiqConstr?dashboard |
PDF: | https://econ-ark.github.io/LiqConstr/LiqConstr.pdf |
Slides: | https://econ-ark.github.io/LiqConstr/LiqConstr-Slides.pdf |
html: | https://econ-ark.github.io/LiqConstr/ |
bibtex: | https://econ-ark.github.io/LiqConstr/LiqConstr-Self.bib |
GitHub: | https://github.com/econ-ark/LiqConstr |
The dashboard will launch a live interactive Jupyter Notebook that uses the Econ-ARK/HARK toolkit to produce all of the paper’s figures (warning: the dashboard may take several minutes to launch).
A large literature has shown that numerical models that take constraints and uncertainty seriously can yield different conclusions than those that characterize traditional models. For example, Kaplan, Moll, and Violante (2018) show that when sufficiently many households have high marginal propensities to consume (MPC’s), a major transmission channel of monetary policy is the ‘indirect income effect’ – a channel of minimal importance in traditional macro models. Similarly, Guerrieri and Lorenzoni (2017) and Bayer, Lütticke, Pham-Dao, and Tjaden (2019) show that tightened borrowing conditions and heightened income risk can help explain the consumption decline during the great recession.
A drawback to numerical solutions is that it is often difficult to know why results come out the way they do. A leading example is in the complex relationship between precautionary saving behavior and liquidity constraints.1 At least since Zeldes (1984), economists working with numerical solutions have known that liquidity constraints can strictly increase precautionary saving under very general circumstances. On the other hand, simulations have sometimes found circumstances under which liquidity constraints and precautionary saving are substitutes. In an early example, Samwick (1995) showed that unconstrained consumers with a precautionary saving motive in a retirement saving model behave in ways qualitatively and quantitatively similar to the behavior of liquidity constrained consumers facing no uncertainty.
This paper provides the theoretical tools to make sense of the interactions between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. The main theoretical innovation is to conceptualize the effects of either constraints or risks in terms of consumption concavity. The advantage of understanding the effects in terms of consumption concavity is that there is a link between more consumption concavity (concavification) and prudence, and therefore also precautionary saving (Kimball, 1990). In particular, we show that prudence of the value function is increased by any concavification of the consumption function regardless of its cause.
Our first main result is to show that the introduction of a constraint at the end of
period causes consumption concavity around the point where the constraint
binds.2
Furthermore, once consumption concavity is created, it propagates back to
periods before
. Carroll and Kimball (1996) showed similar results for the
effects of risks on consumption concavity. Hence, the two papers establish
rigorously that both constraints and risks create a form of consumption
concavity that propagates backward.
Since prudence is heightened when the consumption function is more concave, it follows immediately that when a liquidity constraint is added to a standard consumption problem, the resulting value function exhibits increased prudence around the level of wealth where the constraint becomes binding.3 Constraints induce precaution because constrained agents have less flexibility in responding to shocks when the effects of the shocks cannot be spread out over time. The precautionary motive is heightened by the desire (in the face of risk) to make future constraints less likely to bind.4 This can explain why such a high percentage of households cite precautionary motives as the most important reason for saving (Kennickell and Lusardi, 1999) even though the fraction of households who report actually having been constrained in the past is relatively low (Jappelli, 1990).
After establishing that the introduction of a constraint increases the precautionary saving motive, we show that the introduction of a further future constraint may actually reduce the precautionary saving motive by ‘hiding’ the effects of pre-existing constraints or risks. An existing constraint may be rendered irrelevant at levels of wealth where the new constraint forces more saving than the existing constraint would induce. Identical logic implies that uncertainty can ‘hide’ the effects of a constraint because the consumer may save so much for precautionary reasons that the constraint becomes irrelevant. Thus, the introduction of a new constraint or risk does not generally strengthen the precautionary motive.
A concrete example helps clarify the intuition. A typical perfect foresight model of consumption for a retired consumer with guaranteed income (e.g., ‘Social Security’) implies that a legal constraint on borrowing can make the consumer run their wealth down to zero (thereafter setting consumption equal to income). Now consider modifying the model to incorporate the possibility of large medical expenses near the end of life (e.g. nursing home fees; see Ameriks, Caplin, Laufer, and Van Nieuwerburgh, 2011). Under reasonable assumptions, a consumer facing such a risk may save enough for precautionary reasons to render the no-borrowing constraint irrelevant.
Although there is no general result for the effects of additional constraints or risks when the consumer already faces existing constraints or risks, we can establish how the introduction of all constraints and risks affects the precautionary saving motive. We show that the precautionary saving motive is stronger at every level of wealth5 in the presence of all future risks and constraints than in the case with no risks and constraints. This is because the consumption function is concave everywhere in the presence of all future risks and constraints,6 and since consumption concavity heightens prudence of the value function, the precautionary saving motive is also stronger in the presence of all risks and constraints than in the case with no risks and constraints.
Hence, we can summarize this paper as follows. The effects of liquidity constraints and risks are similar because both stem from the same source: a concavification of the consumption function. The effects work independently, meaning that neither risks nor constraints are necessary to concavify the consumption function. And since a more concave consumption function exhibits heightened prudence, both constraints and risks strengthen the precautionary saving motive. In addition, we explain the apparently contradictory results that constraints and risks in some cases intensify, but in other cases weaken the precautionary saving motive. The central insight is that the effect of introducing an additional constraint or risk depends on whether it weakens the effects of any pre-existing constraints or risks. If it does not interact with any pre-existing constraints or risks, it intensifies the precautionary saving motive. If it does interact, it may weaken the precautionary saving motive at some levels of wealth.
The rest of the paper is structured as follows. To fix notation and ideas, the next section sets out the general theoretical framework. Section 3 then defines what we mean by consumption concavity and shows how consumption concavity propagates backward and heightens prudence of the value function. In Section 4, we show how liquidity constraints cause consumption concavity and thereby also prudence. And Section 5 presents our results on the interactions between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. The final section concludes.
In this section we present the consumer framework underlying all results. We
consider a finitely-lived consumer living from period to
who faces some
future risks and liquidity constraints. The consumer is maximizing the
time-additive present discounted value of utility from consumption
. With
interest and time preference factors
and
, and labeling
consumption
, stochastic labor income
, end-of-period assets
, liquidity
constraint
, and ‘market resources’ (the sum of current income and
spendable wealth from the past)
, the consumer’s problem can be written
as
|
As usual, the recursive nature of the problem makes this equivalent to the Bellman equation
|
We define as the end-of-period value function and rewrite
the problem as7
|
Throughout, what we call ‘the consumption function’ is the mapping from
market resources to consumption. In some of our results we consider utility
functions of the HARA class
| (1) |
with . Note that that (1) also covers the case with quadratic
utility (
).
This section provides a set of tools necessary to prove our main results. We first define what we mean by consumption concavity and show that consumption concavity, once established, propagates back to prior periods. Next, we define an operation we call a ‘counterclockwise concavification’ which describes how either a liquidity constraint or a risk affects the consumption function. The advantage of defining a counterclockwise concavification in such general terms is that we can show that it heightens prudence of the value function irrespective of the source of concavification. Since the relationship between prudence and precautionary saving has already been established in the literature (Kimball, 1990), the tools in this section allow us to establish how liquidity constraints affect precautionary saving in the subsequent sections.
We start by defining what we mean by consumption concavity (CC) and greater consumption concavity.
Definition 1. (Local Consumption Concavity.)
In relation to a utility function with
,
, and non-negative
(
) and non-increasing prudence, a function
has property CC
(alternately, strict CC) over the interval between
and
, where
, if
|
for some increasing function that satisfies concavity (alternately, strict
concavity) over the interval from
to
.
Since (even with constraints) holds by the envelope
theorem,
having property CC (alternately, strict CC) is the same as
having a concave (alternately, strictly concave) consumption function
.8
Note that the definition is restricted to non-negative and non-increasing
prudence. This encompasses most of the commonly used utility functions in
the economics literature (e.g. CRRA, CARA, quadratic). Also, note
that we allow for ‘non-strict’ concavity – that is, linearity – because we
want to include cases such as quadratic utility in which parts of the
consumption function can be linear. Henceforth, unless otherwise noted, we
will drop the cumbersome usage ‘alternately, strict’ – the reader should
assume that what we mean always applies in the two alternate cases in
parallel.
If a function has property local CC at every point, we define it as having property CC globally.
Definition 2. (Global Consumption Concavity.)
A function has property CC in relation to a utility function
with
,
, and non-negative (
) and non-increasing
prudence if
for some monotonically increasing concave
function
.
We now show that once a value function exhibits the property CC in some
period , it will also have the property CC in period
and earlier under
fairly general conditions. Lemma 1 formally provides conditions guaranteeing
this recursive propagation.
Lemma 1. (Recursive Propagation of Consumption Concavity.)
Consider an agent with a HARA utility function satisfying ,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
).
Assume that no liquidity constraint applies at the end of period
and
that the agent faces income risk
. If
exhibits
property (local) CC for all
, then
exhibits property (local) CC at the level of wealth
such that optimal
consumption yields
.
If also exhibits property strict (local) CC for at least
one
, then
exhibits property strict
(local) CC at the level of wealth
where optimal consumption yields
.
See Appendix A for the proof. The basic insight of Lemma 1 is that as long as
the future consumption function is concave for all realizations of , then it is
also concave today. Additionally, if the the future consumption function is
strictly concave for at least one realization of
, then the consumption
function is strictly concave also today.
The last circumstance we define is when a value function exhibits ‘greater’ concavity than another. Later, this will allow us to compare two consumption functions and their respective concavity.
Definition 3. (Greater Consumption Concavity.)
Consider two functions and
that both exhibit property CC with
respect to the same
at a point
for some interval
such that
. Then
exhibits property ‘greater CC’ compared to
if
| (2) |
for all , and property ‘strictly’ greater CC if (2) holds as a strict
inequality.
If and
exist everywhere between
and
, greater concavity of
is equivalent to
being weakly larger in absolute value than
everywhere in
the range from
to
. The strict version of the proposition would
require the inequality to hold strictly over some interval between
and
.
The next concept we introduce is a ‘counterclockwise concavification,’ which describes an operation that makes the modified consumption function more concave than in the original situation. The idea is to think of the consumption function in the modified situation as being a twisted version of the consumption function in the baseline situation, where the kind of twisting allowed is a progressively larger increase in the MPC as the level of market resources gets lower. We call this a ‘counterclockwise concavification’ to describe the sense that at any specific level of market resources, one can think of the increase in the MPC at lower levels of market resources as being a counterclockwise rotation of the lower portion of the consumption function around that level of resources.
Definition 4. (Counterclockwise Concavification.)
Function is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
if
the following conditions hold:
The limits in the definition are necessary to allow for the possibility of discrete drops in the MPC at potential ‘kink points’ in the consumption functions. To understand counterclockwise concavification, it is useful to derive its implied properties.
Lemma 2. (Properties of a Counterclockwise Concavification.)
If is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
and
for all
, then
See Appendix B for the proof. A counterclockwise concavification thus reduces
consumption, increases the MPC, and makes the consumption function more
concave for all levels of market resources below the point of concavification. A
prominent example of a counterclockwise concavification is income risk. Lemma
3 shows, with a slight abuse of notation, that a set of well-known results in the
literature implies that the introduction of a current income risk is an example of
a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function around
.
Lemma 3. (Income Risk Causes Counterclockwise Concavification.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function of the HARA class (1) with
,
,
, and decreasing absolute prudence (
).
Then the consumption function in the presence of a current income risk
is a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function in
the presence of no risk
around
.
Proof. Kimball (1990) shows that positive absolute prudence
ensures that
for all
. Further, decreasing absolute
prudence ensures that the conditions for Corollary 1 in Carroll and
Kimball (1996) are satisfied so that
for all
. The two results
imply that consumption is lower, the MPC is higher, and the consumption
function is more concave everywhere in the case with risk than in the case
with no risk.
is therefore a counterclockwise concavification of
around
. □
Notes: The solid line shows the linear consumption function in the case with no constraints
and no risks. The two dashed lines show the consumption function when we introduce a
constraint and a risk, respectively. The introduction of a constraint is a counterclockwise
concavification of the solid consumption function around , while the introduction of a risk
is a counterclockwise concavification around
.
Figure 1 illustrates two examples of counterclockwise concavifications: the
introduction of a constraint or a risk. In both cases, we start from the
situation with no risk or constraints (solid line). The constraint causes a
counterclockwise concavification around a kink point . Below
,
consumption is lower and the MPC is greater. The introduction of a
risk also generates a counterclockwise concavification of the original
consumption function, but this time around
as described in Lemma
3.
The section above defined a counterclockwise concavification which describes the
effects of either a constraint or a risk on consumption concavity. This section
shows the relationship between consumption concavity and prudence. Our
method is to compare prudence in a baseline case where the consumption
function is to prudence in a modified situation in which the consumption
function
is a counterclockwise concavification of the baseline consumption
function.
The first result relates to the effects of a counterclockwise concavification on
the absolute prudence of the value function, .
Lemma 4. (A Counterclockwise Concavification Increases Prudence.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). If
is
concave and
is a counterclockwise concavification of
, then the
value function associated with
exhibits greater absolute prudence than
the value function associated with
for all
.
See Appendix C for the proof. To understand the effects on prudence of a counterclockwise concavification, note that for a twice differentiable consumption function and thrice differentiable utility function, absolute prudence of the value function is defined as
| (3) |
by the envelope condition. The results in Lemma 4 follow directly. Lemma 4
additionally handles cases where the consumption function is not necessarily
twice differentiable. There are three channels through which a counterclockwise
concavification heightens prudence. First, the increase in consumption concavity
from the counterclockwise concavification itself heightens prudence. Second,
if absolute prudence of the utility function is non-increasing, then the
reduction in consumption (for some states) from the counterclockwise
concavification heightens prudence (at those states). And third, the higher
marginal propensity to consume (MPC) from the counterclockwise
concavification means that any given variation in market resources results
in larger variation in consumption, increasing prudence. The channels
operate separately, implying that a counterclockwise concavification
heightens prudence even if absolute prudence is zero as in the quadratic
case.9
Lemma 4 only provides conditions for when the value function exhibits greater
prudence, but not strictly greater prudence. In particular, the value function
associated with will in some cases (e.g., quadratic utility) have equal
prudence for most
and strictly greater prudence only for some
. In
Lemma 5, we provide conditions for when the value function has strictly greater
prudence.
Lemma 5. (A Counterclockwise Concavification Strictly Increases
Prudence.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). If
is
concave and
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
, then the value function associated with
exhibits strictly greater
prudence than the value function associated with
if the utility
function satisfies
and
or the utility function is quadratic
(
) and
strictly declines at
.
See Appendix D for the proof. For prudent consumers (), the value
function exhibits strictly greater prudence for all
where the counterclockwise
concavification affects consumption. This is because a reduction in consumption
and higher marginal propensity to consume heighten prudence if the utility
function has a positive third derivative and prudence is non-increasing. If the
utility function instead is quadratic, the third derivative is zero and
absolute prudence of the value function does not depend on the level of
consumption or the marginal propensity to consume. In this case, the
counterclockwise concavification only affects prudence at the kink points in the
consumption function (where
strictly declines at
). We have now
defined consumption concavity and the operation called a counterclockwise
concavification. In particular, we have shown that a counterclockwise
concavification heightens prudence, which is related the precautionary saving.
The next section shows how the introduction of a liquidity constraint is a
counterclockwise concavification before we use the tools derived in this section to
provide the link between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving in
Section 5.
This section shows under which conditions liquidity constraints cause consumption concavity. The main conceptual difficulty with liquidity constraints is that the effect of introducing a new constraint depends on already existing constraints. To get around this issue, we introduce the concept of an ordered set of relevant constraints. This allows us to add constraints in such a way that the next constraint does not affect behavior related to pre-existing constraints. Our main result (Theorem 1) is that the introduction of the next constraint from the ordered set of relevant constraints causes a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function. It then follows from the results in Section 3 that the introduction of the next constraint also heightens prudence of the value function.
Recall that we are working with a consumer whose horizon goes from to
.
We define a liquidity constraint dated
as a constraint that requires savings
at the end of period
to be non-negative (the assumption of
non-negativity is without loss of generality as shown in Theorem 1).
We first define what we mean by a kink point which is induced by a
constraint. To have a distinct terminology for the effects of current-period and
future-period constraints, we will use the word ‘binds’ to refer to the potential
effects of a constraint in the period in which it applies and will use the
term ‘impinges’ to describe the effect of a future constraint on current
consumption.
Definition 5. (Kink Point.)
We define a kink point, as the level of market resources at which
constraint
stops binding or impinging on time
consumption.
A kink point corresponds to a transition from a level of market resources where a current constraint binds or a future constraint impinges, to a level of market resources where that constraint no longer binds or impinges. The timing of a constraint relative to other existing constraints matters for the effects of the constraint. We therefore define an ordered set to keep track of the existing constraints.
Definition 6. (An Ordered Set of Relevant Constraints.)
We define as an ordered set of dates at which a relevant constraint
exists. We define
as the last period in which a constraint exists,
as the date of the last period before
in which a constraint exists, and
so on.
is the set of relevant constraints, ordered from the last to the first
constraint. We order them from last to first because a constraint in period
only affects behavior prior to period
(in addition to
itself). The set of
constraints from period
to
summarizes all relevant information in period
. Further, and as discussed below, the effect of imposing the next constraint in
on consumption is unambiguous only if one imposes constraints
chronologically from last to first. For any
, we define
as the
optimal consumption function in period
assuming that the first
constraints in
have been imposed. For example,
is the consumption
function in period
when no constraints have been imposed,
is the
consumption function in period
after the chronologically last constraint has
been imposed, and so on.
, and other functions are defined
correspondingly.
We first consider an initial situation in which a consumer is solving a perfect
foresight optimization problem with a finite horizon that begins in period and
ends in period
. The consumer begins with market resources
and earns
constant income
in each period. Lemma 6 shows how this consumer’s
behavior in period
changes from an initial situation with
constraints to a situation in which
liquidity constraints has been
imposed.
Lemma 6. (Liquidity Constraints Cause Counterclockwise
Concavification.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
,
faces constant income
, and is impatient (
). Assume that
the agent faces a set
of
relevant constraints. Then
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
for
.
See Appendix E for the proof. When we have an ordered set of constraints, ,
the introduction of the next constraint generates a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function.
Lemma 6 analyzes the case where there is a preordained set of constraints
which were applied sequentially in reverse chronological order. We now
examine how behavior will be modified if we add a new date
to the
set of dates at which the consumer is constrained. Call the new set of
dates
with
constraints (one more constraint than before),
and call the consumption rules corresponding to the new set of dates
through
. Now call
the number of constraints in
at dates strictly greater than
. Then note that that
,
because at dates after the date at which the new constraint (number
) is imposed, consumption is the same as in the absence of the new
constraint. Now recall that imposition of the constraint at
causes a
counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function around a new kink
point,
. That is,
is a counterclockwise concavification of
. The most interesting observation, however, is that behavior under
constraints
in periods strictly before
cannot be described as a
counterclockwise concavification of behavior under
. The reason is
that the values of wealth at which the earlier constraints caused kink
points in the consumption functions before period
will not generally
correspond to kink points once the extra constraint has been added.
Notes: is the original consumption function with one constraint that induces a kink point
at
.
is the modified consumption function in where we have introduced one new
constraint. The two constraints affect
through two kink points:
and
. Since we
introduced the new constraint at a later point in time than the current existing constraint, the
future constraint affects the position of the kink induced by the current constraint and the
modified consumption function
is not a counterclockwise concavification of
.
Figure 2 presents an example. The original contains only a single
constraint, at the end of period
, inducing a kink point at
in the
consumption rule
. The expanded set of constraints
adds one constraint
at period
.
induces two kink points in the updated consumption rule
, at
and
. It is true that imposition of the new constraint
causes consumption to be lower than before at every level of wealth
below
. However, this does not imply higher prudence of the value
function at every
. In particular, the original consumption
function is strictly concave at
, while the new consumption function is
linear at
, so prudence is greater before than after imposition of
the new constraint at
. The intuition is straightforward. At levels
of initial wealth below
, the consumer had been planning to end
period
with negative wealth. With the new constraint, the old
plan of ending up with negative wealth is no longer feasible and the
consumer will save more for any given level of current wealth below
,
including
. But the reason
was a kink point in the initial situation
was that it was the level of wealth where consumption would have been
equal to market resources in period
. Now, because of the extra
savings induced by the constraint in
, the period
constraint
will no longer bind for a consumer who begins period
with wealth
. In other words, at wealth
the extra savings induced by the
new constraint prevents the original constraint from being relevant at
. Notice, however, that all constraints that existed in
will remain
relevant at some
under
even after the new constraint is imposed -
they just induce kink points at different levels of market resources than
before (in Figure 2, the first constraint causes a kink at
rather than
).
The preceding analyses required income to be constant, the liquidity constraints
to be of the no-borrowing type, and consumers to be impatient (). We
now relax these requirements. Under these more general circumstances, a
constraint imposed in a given period can render constraints in either earlier or
later periods irrelevant. For example, consider a consumer with CRRA utility
and
who earns income of 1 in each period, but who is required to arrive
at the end of period
with savings of 5. Then a constraint that requires
savings to be greater than zero at the end of period
will have no effect
because the consumer is required by the constraint in period
to end
period
with savings greater than 4. Formally, consider now imposing
the first constraint, which applies in period
. The simplest case,
analyzed before, was a constraint that requires the minimum level of
end-of-period wealth to be
. Here we generalize this to
where
in principle we can allow borrowing by choosing
to be a negative
number. Now for constraint
calculate the kink points for prior periods
from
| (4) |
In addition, for constraint recursively calculate
| (5) |
where is the level of wealth that constraint
requires the
agent to end period
with and
is the lower bound for
the value of consumption permitted by the model (independent of
constraints).10
Now assume that the first
constraints in
have been imposed, and consider
imposing constraint number
, which we assume applies at the end
of period
. The first thing to check is whether constraint number
is relevant given the already-imposed set of constraints. This
is simple: A constraint that requires
will be irrelevant if
, i.e. if one of the existing constraints already implies
that savings must be greater or equal to value required by the new constraint. If
the constraint is irrelevant then the analysis proceeds simply by dropping this
constraint and renumbering the constraints in
so that the former
constraint
becomes constraint
,
becomes
,
and so on. Now consider the other possible problem: That constraint
number
imposed in period
will render irrelevant some of the
constraints that have already been imposed. This too is simple to check:
It will be true if the proposed
for any
and for all
.11
The fix is again simple: Counting down from
, find the smallest value of
for which
. Then we know that constraint
has rendered
constraints
through
irrelevant. The solution is to drop these constraints
from
and start the analysis over again with the modified
. If this set of
procedures is followed until the chronologically earliest relevant constraint has
been imposed, the result will be a
that contains a set of constraints that can
be analyzed as in the simpler case. In particular, proceeding from the final
through
, the imposition of each successive constraint in
now causes a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption
function around successively lower values of wealth as progressively earlier
constraints are applied and the result is again a piecewise linear and strictly
concave consumption function with the number of kink points equal
to the number of constraints that are relevant at any feasible level of
wealth in period
. The preceding discussion establishes the following
result:
Theorem 1. (Liquidity Constraints Cause Counterclockwise
Concavification.)
Consider an agent in period who has a utility function with
,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
).
Assume that the agent faces a set
of
relevant constraints. Then
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
.
Theorem 1 is a generalization of Lemma 6. Even if we relax the assumptions that
income is constant and the agent is impatient, the imposition of an extra (more
general) constraint increases absolute prudence of the value function as long as
we are careful when we select the set of relevant constraints. For an agent
that only faces liquidity constraints, but no risk, the shape of the consumption
function is piecewise linear. Since the consumption function is piecewise linear,
the new consumption function,
is not necessarily strictly
more concave than
for all
. This is where the concept of
counterclockwise concavification is useful. Even though
is not
strictly more concave than
everywhere, it is a counterclockwise
concavification and we can apply Lemma 4 and 5 to show that the introduction
of the next liquidity constraint increases absolute prudence of the value
function.
Corollary 1. (Liquidity Constraints Increase Prudence.)
Consider an agent in period who has a utility function with
,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
).
Assume that the agent faces a set
of
relevant constraints. When
constraints have been imposed, the imposition of constraint
strictly increases absolute prudence of the agent’s value function if
the utility function satisfies
and
or if
and
strictly declines at
.
Proof. By Theorem 1, the imposition of constraint constitutes
a counterclockwise concavification of
. By Lemma 4 and 5,
such a concavification (strictly) increases absolute prudence of the value
function. □
The preceding sections established the relationship between liquidity constraints, consumption concavity, and prudence. This section derives the last step to understand the relationship between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. First, we explain how prudence of the value function affects precautionary saving. Theorem 2 then shows how the introduction of an additional constraint induces agents to increase precautionary saving when they face a current risk. The results in Theorem 2 cannot be generalized to an added risk or liquidity constraint in a later time period because it may hide or alter the effects of current constraints or risks and thereby affect local precautionary saving. The main conceptual issue with having both risks and constraints is that the trick with the relevant constraints applied in Section 4 no longer applies in a setting with risk because constraints may be relevant for some sample paths. However, we still derive our most general result in Theorem 3: the introduction of an additional risk results in more precautionary saving in the presence of all future risks and constraints than in the case with no future risks and constraints.
We begin by defining two marginal value functions and
which
are convex, downward sloping, and continuous in wealth,
. We consider a
risk
with support
, and follow Kimball (1990) by defining the
Compensating Precautionary Premia (CPP) as the values
and
such
that
|
The CPP can be interpreted as the additional resources an agent requires to be indifferent between accepting the risk and not accepting the risk. The relevant part of Pratt (1964)’s Theorem 1 as reinterpreted using Kimball (1990)’s Lemma (p. 57) can be restated as
Lemma 7. Let and
be absolute prudence of the value functions
and
respectively at
,12
and let
and
be the respective compensating precautionary premia
associated with imposition of a given risk
as per (6). Then the following
conditions are equivalent:
Lemma 7 establishes that greater prudence is equivalent to inducing
a greater precautionary premium. For our purpose, it means that our
results above on absolute prudence also imply that the precautionary
premium is higher. Hence, a more prudent consumer requires a
higher compensation to be indifferent about facing the risk or
not.13
We now take up the question of how the introduction of a risk that will be
realized at the beginning of period
affects consumption in period
in the
presence and in the absence of a subsequent constraint. To simplify the
discussion, consider a consumer for whom
, with mean income
in
period
. Assume that the realization of the risk
will be some value
with support [
,
], and signify a decision rule that takes account of the
presence of the immediate risk by a
. Further, define
as the lowest
level of market resources required for the liquidity constraint to never
bind.
Definition 7. (Wealth Limit.) is the level of wealth such that an agent who faces risk
and
constraints saves enough to guarantee that constraint
will never bind in
period
. Its value is given by:
| (6) |
How to read this limit: is the level of wealth at which constraint
makes the transition from binding to not binding in period
.
is the level of wealth in period
that ensures that
constraint
does not bind in period
even with the worst possible
draw,
.
We must be careful to check that is inside the set of feasible
values of
(e.g. positive for consumers with CRRA utility). If this is not true
for some level of market resources, then the constraint is irrelevant because the
restriction imposed by the risk is more stringent than the restriction imposed by
the constraint.
We are now in a position to analyze the relationship between precautionary
saving and liquidity constraints. Our first result regards the effect of an
additional constraint on the precautionary saving of a household facing risk at
the beginning of period .
Theorem 2. (Liquidity Constraints Increase Precautionary Saving.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
), and who faces the risk,
. Assume that the agent faces a set
of N relevant constraints and
. Then
| (7) |
and the inequality is strict if wealth is less than the level that ensures that
constraint never binds (
).
See Appendix F for the proof. Theorem 2 shows that the introduction of the
next constraint induces the agent to save more for precautionary reasons in
response to an immediate risk as long as there is a positive probability that the
next constraint will bind. Theorem 2 can be generalized to period if there
is no risk or constraint between period
and
by defining
as the
wealth level at which the agent will arrive in the beginning of period
with
wealth
.
To illustrate the result in Theorem 2, Figure 3 shows an example of optimal
consumption rules in period under different combinations of an immediate
risk (realized at the beginning of period
) and a future constraint
(applying at the end of period
).
Notes: is the consumption function with no constraint and no risk,
is the
consumption function with no constraint and a risk that is realized at the beginning of period
,
is the consumption function with one constraint in period
and no risk, and
is the consumption function with one constraint in period
and a risk that is
realized at the beginning of period
. The figure illustrates that the vertical distance
between
and
is always greater than the vertical distance between
and
for
.
The thinner loci reflect behavior of consumers who face the future constraint,
and the dashed loci reflect behavior of consumers who face the immediate risk.
For levels of wealth above where the future constraint stops impinging on
current behavior for perfect foresight consumers, behavior of the constrained
and unconstrained perfect foresight consumers is the same. Similarly,
for levels of wealth above
beyond which the probability
of the future constraint binding is zero. For both constrained and unconstrained
consumers, the introduction of the risk reduces the level of consumption (the
dashed loci are below their solid counterparts). The significance of Theorem
2 in this context is that for levels of wealth below
, the vertical
distance between the solid and the dashed loci is greater for the constrained
(thin line) than for the unconstrained (thick line) consumers because of
the interaction between the liquidity constraint and the precautionary
motive.
The result in Theorem 2 is limited to the effects of an additional constraint when
a household faces income risk that is realized at the beginning of period .
One might think that this could be generalized to a proposition that
precautionary saving increases if we for example impose an immediate constraint
or an earlier risk, or generally impose multiple constraints or risks. However, it
turns out that the answer is “not necessarily” to all these possible scenarios. The
insight here is that it is no longer possible to use the trick of the relevant
constraints or risks in the previous section. In a perfect-foresight environment as
in Section 4 and Theorem 2, there was a stark demarcation between
relevant and irrelevant constraints. In an environment with risk, this no
longer holds because in the presence of risk, constraints and risks may be
relevant for some sample paths. The additional constraints and risks may
therefore reduce precautionary saving for some levels of
and we cannot
derive more general results on additional risks or constraints. We provide
two examples to illustrate this: an immediate constraint and an earlier
risk.
To describe these examples, we need a last bit of notation. Define as the
consumption function in period
assuming that the first
constraints and
the first
risks have been imposed, counting risks, like constraints,
backwards from period
. All other functions are defined correspondingly.
We will continue to use the notation
to designate the effects of
imposition of a single immediate risk realized at the beginning of period
.
Notes: is the consumption function with no constraint and no risk,
is the
consumption function with no constraint and one future risk in
,
is the
consumption function with one immediate constraint and no risk, and
is the consumption
function with one immediate constraint and one future risk in
. The figure illustrates
that the future risk has no effect on consumption when
because the immediate
constraint hides the effect of the future risk.
Consider a situation in which no constraint applies between and
illustrated in Figure 4. Since
designates the consumption rule that will be
optimal prior to imposing the period-
constraint, the consumption rule
imposing the constraint will be
. Now define the level
of market resources below which the period
constraint binds for a
consumer not facing the risk as
For values of
, analysis of
the effects of the risk is identical to analysis in the previous subsection.
For levels of market resources
where the constraint binds
both in the presence and the absence of the immediate risk, we have
. Hence, for consumers with wealth below
, the
introduction of the risk in period
has no effect on consumption in
, because for these levels of savings at the end of
, the consumers
where constrained before the risk was imposed and remain constrained
afterwards. Hence, the immediate constraint hides the risk from view
and the precautionary saving in response to the risk is higher in the
absence of the constraint than in the presence of the constraint when
.
Consider now the question of how the addition of a risk that will be
realized at the beginning of period
affects the consumption function
at the beginning of period
, in the absence of any constraint at
the beginning of period
. The question is whether we can say that
the introduction of the risk
has a greater precautionary effect on
consumption in the presence of the subsequent risk
than in its
absence?
The answer again is “not necessarily.” To see why, we present an example in
Appendix G of a CRRA utility problem in which in a certain limit the
introduction of a risk produced an effect on the consumption function that is
indistinguishable from the effect of a liquidity constraint. If the risk is of this
liquidity-constraint-indistinguishable form, then the logic of the previous
subsection applies: For some levels of wealth, the introduction of the
risk at
can weaken the precautionary effect of any risks at
or
later.
It might seem that the previous subsection implies that little useful can be said about the precautionary effects of introducing a new risk in the presence of preexisting constraints and risks. It turns out, however, that there is one useful result about the introduction of all risks and constraints.
Theorem 3. (Liquidity Constraints and Risks Increase Precautionary Saving.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). Then the introduction of a
risk
has a greater precautionary effect on period
consumption in the
presence of all future risks and constraints than in the absence of any future risks
and constraints, i.e.
| (8) |
at levels of period- market resources
such that in the absence of the new
risk the consumer is not constrained in the current period
and
in the presence of the risk there is a positive probability that some future
constraint will bind.
Appendix H presents the proof. A fair summary of this theorem is that in most circumstances the presence of future constraints and risks does increase the amount of precautionary saving induced by the introduction of a given new risk. The primary circumstance under which this should not be expected is for levels of wealth at which the consumer was constrained even in the absence of the new risk. There is no guarantee that the new risk will produce a sufficiently intense precautionary saving motive to move the initially-constrained consumer off his constraint. If it does, the effect will be precautionary, but it is possible that no effect will occur.
Our last result is part of the proof of Theorem 3, but we state it explicitly as a corollary.
Corollary 2. (Liquidity Constraints and Risk Cause Counterclockwise
Concavification.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). Then the
consumption function in the presence of
future risks and
constraints
is a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function with
no risk and no constraints
.
Corollary 2 states that the consumption function in the presence of all future risks and constraints is a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function with no risks or constraints. In other words, the consumption function is concave in the presence of all future risks and constraints.
The central message of this paper is that the effects of liquidity constraints and of future risks on precautionary saving are similar because the introduction of either a liquidity constraints or a risk makes the consumption function more concave than the perfect foresight consumption function. Such an increase in concavity heightens prudence, inducing consumers at any affected level of wealth to save more for precautionary reasons.
In addition, we provide an explanation of apparently contradictory results: That constraints in some cases intensify and in other cases weaken those motives. The insight here is that the effect of introducing a constraint or risk depends on whether it weakens the effect of any pre-existing constraints or risks. If the new constraint or risk does not interact in any way with existing constraints or risks, it intensifies the precautionary saving motive. If it ‘hides’ or moves the effect of any existing constraints or risks, it may weaken the precautionary saving motive at some levels of market resources.
Proof. First, to facilitate readability of the proof, we assume that
with no loss of generality. Our goal is to prove that
if
for all realizations of
.
The proof proceeds in two steps. First, we show that property CC
is preserved through the expectation operator (vertical aggregation),
i.e. that
if
for
all realizations of
. Second, we show that property CC is preserved
through the value function operator (horizontal aggregation), i.e. that
if
. Throughout
the proof, the first order condition holds with equality since no liquidity
constraint applies at the end of period
.
Step 1: Vertical aggregation
We show that consumption concavity is preserved under vertical aggregation for
three cases of the HARA utility function with (
)
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). The three cases
are
| (9) |
Case I (, CRRA.) We will show that concavity is preserved under
vertical aggregation for
to avoid clutter, but the results hold for all affine
transformations,
, with
. Concavity of
implies
that
| (10) |
for all if
with
. Since this holds for
all
, we know that
| (11) |
We now apply Minkowski’s inequality (see e.g. Beckenbach and Bellman, 1983,
Theorem 3) which says that for and a scalar
| (12) |
This implies that for (CRRA)
| (13) |
if and
. Thus
which implies that
| (14) |
Thus, defining , we get
for all , where the inequality is strict if
is strictly concave for at least
one realization of
. Case II (
, CARA). For the exponential case,
property CC holds at
if
|
for some which is strictly concave at
. We set
to reduce
clutter, but results hold for
. Consider first a case where
is linear
over the range of possible values of
, then
|
which is linear in since the second term is a constant. Now consider a
value of
for which
is strictly concave for at least one
realization of
. Global weak concavity of
tells us that for every
|
Meanwhile, the arithmetic-geometric mean inequality states that for positive
and
, if
and
, then
|
implying that
|
where the expression holds with equality only if is proportional to
.
Substituting in
and
, this means
that
|
and we can substitute for the LHS from (15), obtaining
|
which holds with equality only when is a constant.
This will only happen if
is constant, which
(given that the MPC is strictly positive everywhere) requires
to
be linear for
. Hence,
|
where the inequality is strict for an from which
is strictly concave for
some realization of
.
Case III (, Quadratic). In the quadratic case, linearity of marginal
utility implies that
|
so is simply the weighted sum of a set of concave functions where the
weights correspond to the probabilities of the various possible outcomes for
. The sum of concave functions is itself concave. And if additionally the
consumption function is strictly concave at any point, the weighted sum is also
strictly concave.
Step 2: Horizontal aggregation:
We now proceed with horizontal aggregation, namely how concavity is preserved
through the value function operation. Assume that at point
,
then the first order condition implies that
| (15) |
for some monotonically increasing that satisfies
| (16) |
for any , and
.
In addition, we know that the first order condition holds with equality such
that which implies that
. Using
this equation, we get
which implies that is a convex function.
Use the budget constraint to define
Now, since is a convex function, and
is the sum of a convex and a
linear function, it is also a convex function satisfying
|
so is concave.
Note that the proof of horizontal aggregation works for any utility function
with and
when
=
= 1. However, for the more general
case where
or
are not equal to one, we need the HARA property that
multiplying
by a constant corresponds to a linear transformation of
.
Strict Consumption Concavity. When exhibits the property
strict CC for at least one
, we know that
also
exhibits the property strict CC from the proof of vertical aggregation. Then,
equation (16) holds with strict inequality, and this strict inequality goes through
the proof of horizontal aggregation, implying that equation (17) holds with strict
inequality. Hence,
is strictly concave if
is concave for all
realizations of
and strictly concave for at least one realization of
. □
Proof. First, condition 2 and 4 in Definition 4 imply that
for
for
a small
. Condition 3 then ensures that
holds for all
(equivalently
). Second, condition 1
and the fact that
for
implies that
for
. Third, condition 3 in Definition
4 implies that
Proof. By the envelope theorem, we know that
| (17) |
Differentiating with respect to yields
| (18) |
Since is concave, it has left-hand and right-hand derivatives at every
point, though the left-hand and right-hand derivatives may not be equal.
Equation (18) should be interpreted as applying the left-hand and right-hand
derivatives separately. (Reading (18) in this way implies that
;
therefore
). Taking another derivative can run afoul of the
possible discontinuity in
that we will show below can arise from liquidity
constraints. We therefore consider two cases: (i)
exists and (ii)
does not exist.
Case I: ( exists.)
In the case where exists, we can take another derivative
| (19) |
Absolute prudence of the value function is thus defined as
|
From the assumption that is a counterclockwise concavification of
,
we know from Lemma 2 that
and
. Furthermore,
since
is non-increasing, we know that
. As a
result,
.
The second part of the absolute prudence expression, , is a measure
of the curvature of the consumption function. Since the consumption function is
concave,
is a measure of the degree of concavity. Formally, if one has
two functions,
and
, that are both increasing and concave functions,
then the concave transformation
always has more curvature than
.14
A counterclockwise concavification is an example of such a
. Hence,
. Then
Case II: ( does not exist.)
Informally, if nonexistence is caused by a constraint binding at , the effect
will be a discrete decline in the marginal propensity to consume at
, which
can be thought of as
, implying positive infinite prudence at that
point (see (20)). Formally, if
does not exist, greater prudence of
than
is given by
being a decreasing function of
. This is defined
as
| (21) |
The second factor, , is weakly decreasing in
by the property of a
counterclockwise concavification. At any specific value of
where
does
not exist because the left and right hand values of
are different, we say that
is decreasing if
| (22) |
As for the first factor, note that nonexistence of and/or
do
not spring from nonexistence of either
or
(for our
purposes, when the left and right derivatives of
differ at a point, the
relevant derivative is the one coming from the left; rather than carry around the
cumbersome limit notation, read the following derivation as applying to the left
derivative). To discover whether
is decreasing we differentiate
(recall that the log is a monotonically decreasing transformation
so the derivative of the log of a function always has the same sign as the
derivative of the function):
This will be negative if
|
Recall from Lemma 2 that and
so
non-increasing absolute prudence of the utility function ensures that
. Hence the LHS is always greater or equal to the RHS
of equation (23).
□
Proof. We prove each statement in Lemma 5 separately.
Case I: (.)
If , a counterclockwise concavification around
implies that
and
for all
. Then
| (23) |
Note that this condition is sufficient to prove Lemma 5 for the case where
does not exist since it then satisfies (23). In the case where
does
exist, we know that
| (24) |
from the proof of Lemma 4. Hence,
and Lemma 5 holds in the case with and
.
Case II: (.)
The quadratic case requires a different approach. Note first that the
conditions in Lemma 5 hold only below the bliss point for quadratic utility. In
addition, since , strict inequality between the prudence of
and
the prudence of
hold only at those points where
is strictly
concave.
Recall from the proof of Lemma 4 that greater prudence of than
occurs if
is decreasing in
. In the quadratic case
| (25) |
where the second equality follows since is constant with quadratic utility.
Thus, prudence is strictly greater in the modified case only if
strictly
declines in
. □
We prove Lemma 6 by induction in two steps. First, we show that all results
in Lemma 6 hold when we add the first constraint. The second step
is then to show that the results hold when we go from to
constraints.
Lemma 8.
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
,
faces constant income, is impatient (
), and has a finite life. Then
.
Proof. The marginal propensity to consume in period can be obtained from
the MPC in period
from the Euler equation
|
Differentiating both sides with respect to and omitting arguments to reduce
clutter we obtain
|
Since ensures that
, we know that
| (26) |
Furthermore, we know that
| (27) |
since is the MPC for an infinitely-lived agent with
. Hence,
| (28) |
and it follows that . □
Lemma 9. (Consumption with one Liquidity Constraint.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
,
faces constant income,
, and is impatient,
. Assume that the
agent faces a set
of one relevant constraint. Then
is a
counterclockwise concavification of
around
.
Proof. We now prove Lemma 9 by first showing that the consumption
function including the constraint at the end of period is a
counterclockwise concavification of the unconstrained consumption function
in period
. Next, we show how the constraint further implies that
the consumption function including the constraint is a counterclockwise
concavification of the unconstrained consumption function in periods prior
to
.
We first define as the time period of the constraint. Note first that
consumption is unaffected by the constraint for all periods after
, i.e.
for any
. For period
, we can calculate the level of
consumption at which the constraint binds by realizing that a consumer for
whom the constraint binds will save nothing and therefore arrive in the next
period with no wealth. Further, the maximum amount of consumption at which
the constraint binds will satisfy the Euler equation (only points where the
constraint is strictly binding violate the Euler equation; the point on the cusp
does not). Thus, we define
as the maximum level of consumption in period
at which the agent leaves no wealth for the next period, i.e. the constraint
stops binding:
|
and the level of wealth at which the constraint stops binding can be obtained from
| (29) |
Below this level of wealth, we have so the MPC is one, while
above it we have
where the MPC equals the constant MPC
for an unconstrained perfect foresight optimization problem with a horizon of
. Thus,
satisfies our definition of a counterclockwise concavification
of
around
.
Further, we can obtain the value of period consumption at which
the period
constraint stops impinging on period
behavior
from
|
and we can obtain via the analogue to (29). Iteration generates the
remaining
and
values back to period
.
Now consider the behavior of a consumer in period with a level of
wealth
. This consumer knows he will be constrained and will spend
all of his resources next period, so at
his behavior will be identical to the
behavior of a consumer whose entire horizon ends at time
. As shown in step
I, the MPC always declines with horizon. The MPC for this consumer is
therefore strictly greater than the MPC of the unconstrained consumer whose
horizon ends at
. Thus, in each period before
, the consumption
function
generated by imposition of the constraint constitutes a
counterclockwise concavification of the unconstrained consumption function
around the kink point
. □
We have now shown the results in Lemma 6 for . The last step is to
show that they also hold for
when they hold strictly for
. Consider
imposing the
’st constraint and suppose for concreteness that it applies at
the end of period
. It will stop binding at a level of consumption defined
by
|
This means that the constraint is relevant: The pre-existing constraint does
not force the consumer to do so much saving in period
that the
’st
constraint fails to bind.
The prior-period levels of consumption and wealth at which constraint
stops impinging on consumption can again be calculated recursively
from
|
Furthermore, once again we can think of the constraint as terminating
the horizon of a finite-horizon consumer in an earlier period than it is
terminated for the less-constrained consumer, with the implication that the
MPC below is strictly greater than the MPC above
.
Thus, the consumption function
constitutes a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function
around the kink point
.
Proof.
Our proof proceeds by constructing the behavior of consumers facing the risk
from the behavior of the corresponding perfect foresight consumers. We consider
matters from the perspective of some level of wealth for the perfect foresight
consumers. Because the same marginal utility function
applies to all
four consumption rules, the Compensating Precautionary Premia,
and
, associated with the introduction of the risk
must
satisfy
|
Define the amounts of precautionary saving induced by the risk at an
arbitrary level of wealth
in the two cases as
| (30) |
where the mnemonic is that the first two letters of the Greek letter psi stand for precautionary saving.
We can rewrite the last (resp. the first) equation of (30) as
|
which implies that
|
and
|
so the difference between precautionary saving for the consumer facing
constraints and the one facing
constraints at
is
|
If we can show that (31) is a positive number for all feasible levels of
satisfying
, then we have proven Theorem 2. We know that
the marginal propensity to consume is always strictly positive and that
15
so to prove that (31) is strictly positive, we need to show one of two sufficient
conditions:
Now, since , we know that
from Jensen’s inequality. Hence,
since
. The first integral in (31) is therefore strictly
positive as long as
, which is true for
by Lemma
6.
For , we know that
so the first integral in (31) is
always zero. For the second integral in (31) to be strictly positive, we need to
show that
.
First define the perfect foresight consumption functions as
|
where since
. Recall also the definitions of
and
:
|
Now recall that Lemma 7 tells us that if absolute prudence of
is identical to absolute prudence of
for every realization of
,
then
. This is true if
for all possible realizations
of
, i.e. that the agent is unconstrained for all realizations of the risk.
We defined this limit as
. We therefore know that
if
.
For all levels of wealth below this limit (), there exist
realizations of
such that constraint
will bind in period
. The
agent will require a higher precautionary premia when facing constraint
in addition to the
constraints already in the set, implying that
.
Equation (31) is therefore strictly positive if
and we have proven
Theorem 2. □
This appendix repeats an illustration from appendix G of Carroll Forthcoming. (We make no claim to novelty of this point; it is here only to aid the intuition of the reader).
In this appendix, we provide an example where the introduction of risk
resembles the introduction of a constraint. Consider the second-to-last period of
life for two risk-averse CRRA utility consumers and assume for simplicity that
.
The first consumer is subject to a liquidity constraint , and
earns non-stochastic income of
in period
. This consumer’s saving rule
will be
|
The second consumer is not subject to a liquidity constraint, but faces a stochastic income process,
|
If we write the consumption rule for the unconstrained consumer facing the
risk as the key result is that in the limit as
, behavior of the two
consumers becomes the same. That is, defining
as the optimal saving
rule for the consumer facing the risk,
|
for every .
To see this, start with the Euler equations for the two consumers given wealth
,
|
Consider first the case where is large enough that the constraint does not
bind for the constrained consumer,
. In this case the limit of the Euler
equation for the second consumer is identical to the Euler equation for the first
consumer (because for
savings are positive for the consumer facing the
risk, implying that the limit of the first
term on the RHS of the second line
of (31) is finite). Thus the limit of the second equation in (31) is the first
equation in (31) for
.
Now consider the case where so that the first consumer would be
constrained. This consumer spends her entire resources
, and by the
definition of the constraint we know that
| (31) |
Now consider the consumer facing the risk. If this consumer were to save
exactly zero and then experienced the bad shock in period , she would have
an infinite marginal utility (the Inada condition). This cannot satisfy the
Euler-equation as long as
. Therefore we know that for any
and
any
the consumer will save some positive amount. For a fixed
,
hypothesize that there is some
such that no matter how small
became
the consumer would always choose to save at least
. But for any
, the limit
of the RHS of the second line of (31) is
. We know from concavity of
the utility function that
and we know from (31) that
, so as
there must always come a point
at which the consumer can improve her total utility by shifting some
resources from the future to the present, i.e. by saving less. Since this
argument holds for any
it demonstrates that as
goes to zero
there is no positive level of saving that would make the consumer better
off. But saving of zero or a negative amount is ruled out by the Inada
condition at
. Hence saving must approach, but never equal, zero as
.
Thus, we have shown that for and for
in the limit as
the consumer facing the risk but no constraint behaves identically to the
consumer facing the constraint but no risk. This argument can be generalized to
show that for the CRRA utility consumer, spending must always be strictly
less than the sum of current wealth and the minimum possible value of
human wealth. Thus, the addition of a risk to the problem can rule out
certain levels of wealth as feasible, and can also render either future or
past constraints irrelevant, just as the imposition of a new constraint
can.
Proof. To simplify notation and without loss of generality, we assume that
when an agent faces constraints and
risks, there are one constraint
and one risk for each time period. For example, if
faces
future
risks and
future constraints, then the next period consumption function
is
(and
). Note that we can transform any problem into
this notation by filling in with degenerate risks and non-binding constraints.
However, for Theorem 3 to hold with strict inequality, we need to assume
that there is at least one relevant future risk and one relevant constraint.
We know that either the introduction of risk or a introduction of a constraint results in a counterclockwise concavification of the original consumption function. However, this is only true when we introduce risks in the absence of constraints (Lemma 3) and when we introduce constraints in the absence of risk (see Theorem 1). In this proof, we therefore need to show that the introduction of all risks and constraints is a counterclockwise concavification of the linear case with no risks and constraints.
Here is our proof strategy. We define a set
| (32) |
where Theorem 3 holds in period when we introduce a risk at the beginning
of period
. This is defined as the set where precautionary saving induced
by a risk that is realized at the beginning of period
is greater
in the presence of all risks and constraints than in the unconstrained
case.
In order to show that the set is non-empty, we build it up
recursively, starting from period
and adding one constraint or one risk
for each time period. The key to the proof is to understand that the
introduction of risks or constraints will never fully reverse the effects
of all other risks and constraints, even though they sometimes reduce
absolute prudence for some levels of wealth because risks and constraints
can mask the effects of future risks and constraints. Hence, the new
consumption function must still be a counterclockwise concavification of the
consumption function with no risks and constraints for some levels of
wealth.
Since a counterclockwise concavification increases prudence by Lemma 4, and higher prudence increases precautionary saving by Lemma 7, our required set can be redefined as
where we add the last condition, to avoid the possibility that
some constraint binds such that the agent does not increase precautionary
saving. In words:
is the set where the consumption function is a
counterclockwise concavification of
and no constraint is strictly binding.
We construct the set recursively for two different cases: CARA and all
other type of utility functions. We start with the non-CARA utility
functions.
First add the last constraint. The set is then since we know that
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
but that
the consumer is constrained below this point.
We next add the risk at the beginning of period . To construct the new set,
we note three things. First, by Lemma 1, (strict) consumption concavity is
recursively propagated for all values of wealth where there is a positive
probability that the constraint can bind, i.e.
| (33) |
has property strict CC, while it has non-strict property for all possible
values of
. Further, we know from Theorem 2 (rearrange equation (7))
that
Third, we know that since
for
,
, and that
is concave
while
is linear. Hence,
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around the minimum value of wealth when the constraint will never bind
and the new set is
We can now add the next constraint. The consumption function now
has two kink points, and
. We know again from Lemma
1 that consumption concavity is preserved when we add a constraint,
and strict consumption concavity is preserved for all values of wealth at
which a future constraint might bind. Further, we know from Theorem 2
that
Third, ,
, and
we know that if
is concave while
is linear, then
.
which is a counterclockwise concavification
of
around the minimum level of wealth at which the first constraint
will never impinge on time
consumption,
, and the new set
is
| (34) |
It is now time to add the next risk. The argument is similar. We still know
that (strict) consumption concavity is recursively propagated and that
. Further, we can think of the addition of
two risks over two periods as adding one risk that is realized over two periods.
Hence, the results from Theorem 2 must hold also for the addition of multiple
risks so we have
Hence, we again know that .
is thus a
counterclockwise concavification of
around the level of wealth at
minimum value of wealth when the last constraint will never bind. The new set
is therefore
| (35) |
Doing this recursively and defining as the minimum value of wealth
beyond which constraint
will never bind, the set of wealth levels at which
Theorem 3 holds can be defined as
| (36) |
In words, precautionary saving is higher if there is a positive probability that some future constraint could bind and the consumer is not constrained today.
The last requirement is to define the set also for the CARA utility function. The
problem with CARA utility is that
where
is some positive constant. We can therefore not use the same
arguments as in the preceding proof. However, by realizing that equation (7) in
the CARA case can be defined as
where the last inequality follows since precautionary saving is always higher than in the constant limit in the presence of constraints. We can therefore rearrange to get
which implies that the arguments in the preceding section goes through also for CARA utility with this slight modification. □
Ameriks, John, Andrew Caplin, Steven Laufer, and Stijn Van Nieuwerburgh (2011): “The Joy Of Giving Or Assisted Living? Using Strategic Surveys To Separate Public Care Aversion From Bequest Motives,” The Journal of Finance, 66(2), 519–561.
Bayer, Christian, Ralph Lütticke, Lien Pham-Dao, and Volker Tjaden (2019): “Precautionary savings, illiquid assets, and the aggregate consequences of shocks to household income risk,” Econometrica, 87(1), 255–290.
Beckenbach, Edwin F, and Richard Bellman (1983): Inequalities, vol. 30. Springer, reprint edn.
Carroll, Christopher D. (Forthcoming): “Theoretical Foundations of Buffer Stock Saving,” Quantitative Economics.
Carroll, Christopher D., and Miles S. Kimball (1996): “On the Concavity of the Consumption Function,” Econometrica, 64(4), 981–992, http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/concavity.pdf.
Deaton, Angus S. (1991): “Saving and Liquidity Constraints,” Econometrica, 59, 1221–1248, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2938366.
Druedahl, Jeppe, and Casper Nordal Jørgensen (2018): “Precautionary borrowing and the credit card debt puzzle,” Quantitative Economics, 9(2), 785–823.
Fulford, Scott L (2015): “How important is variability in consumer credit limits?,” Journal of Monetary Economics, 72, 42–63.
Guerrieri, Veronica, and Guido Lorenzoni (2017): “Credit crises, precautionary savings, and the liquidity trap,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 132(3), 1427–1467.
Holm, Martin Blomhoff (2018): “Consumption with liquidity constraints: An analytical characterization,” Economics Letters, 167, 40–42.
Jappelli, Tullio (1990): “Who is Credit Constrained in the U.S. Economy?,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 105(1), 219–34.
Kaplan, Greg, Benjamin Moll, and Giovanni L. Violante (2018): “Monetary Policy According to HANK,” American Economic Review, 108(3), 697–743.
Kennickell, Arthur B., and Annamaria Lusardi (1999): “Assessing the Importance of the Precautionary Saving Motive: Evidence from the 1995 SCF,” Manuscript, Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System.
Kimball, Miles S. (1990): “Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the Large,” Econometrica, 58, 53–73.
Lee, Jeong-Joon, and Yasuyuki Sawada (2007): “The degree of precautionary saving: A reexamination,” Economics Letters, 96(2), 196–201.
__________ (2010): “Precautionary saving under liquidity constraints: Evidence from rural Pakistan,” Journal of Development Economics, 91(1), 77–86.
Nishiyama, Shin-Ichi, and Ryo Kato (2012): “On the Concavity of the Consumption Function with a Quadratic Utility under Liquidity Constraints,” Theoretical Economics Letters, 2(05), 566.
Park, Myung-Ho (2006): “An analytical solution to the inverse consumption function with liquidity constraints,” Economics Letters, 92(3), 389–394.
Pratt, John W. (1964): “Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large,” Econometrica, 32, 122–136.
Samwick, Andrew A. (1995): “The Limited Offset Between Pension Wealth and Other Private Wealth: Implications of Buffer-Stock Saving,” Manuscript, Department of Economics, Dartmouth College.
Seater, John J (1997): “An optimal control solution to the liquidity constraint problem,” Economics Letters, 54(2), 127–134.
Zeldes, Stephen P. (1984): “Optimal Consumption with Stochastic Income,” Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.